The notion of likeness in Aristotle's theory of sense-perception
The nature, the reason and the science of man: a new edition of Leonardo da Vinci'...
Grant number: | 20/15938-8 |
Support Opportunities: | Scholarships abroad - Research |
Start date: | December 17, 2021 |
End date: | June 16, 2022 |
Field of knowledge: | Humanities - Philosophy - History of Philosophy |
Principal Investigator: | Evan Robert Keeling |
Grantee: | Evan Robert Keeling |
Host Investigator: | Jennifer Elaine Whiting |
Host Institution: | Faculdade de Filosofia, Letras e Ciências Humanas (FFLCH). Universidade de São Paulo (USP). São Paulo , SP, Brazil |
Institution abroad: | University of Pittsburgh (Pitt), United States |
Abstract The aim of this project is to understand Aristotle's theory of color. I aim to answer the following main questions: What is the nature of colors for Aristotle? What is it for an object to be colored? What colors did he recognize, and what is required for these colors to be realized? Which colors did he take as primary or basic, and in what sense? How do non-basic colors come to be? Colors are naturally perceptible, but do they have a non-perceptual nature as well? And what does this tell us about Aristotle's theories of perception and epistemology? Some preliminary answers are as follows. Colors are qualities, especially of determinate objects but they are also transmitted by indeterminate media like air and water. When they are not being perceived, they are first actualities in Aristotle's scheme. The colors of determinate objects (the red of a tomato, say) are able to change an actually transparent medium (for example, the air surrounding it). This medium is then able to change a potentially seeing eye, which then becomes an actually seeing eye and transmits the color to the central sense organ. The object, the medium, and the eye are able to do this because they all partake in transparency. Transparency, it seems, is due to something bright such as light. In the medium, it is due to the presence of light. In objects like tomatoes, it seems that it is also due to light, though they admit light to a lesser degree. Colors themselves range from leukon to melan, which are usually taken as white and black, but arguably better understood as bright and dark. Aristotle recognizes yellow, green, blue, red, purple, and grey as falling between these. The main color spectrum seems, therefore, to be based on the primary distinction between light and dark. But it is not the only way colors differ from one another: the difference between yellow and green, say, is qualitative and not only quantitive. As the primary object of vision, understanding colors and the many ways they come to be and come to be seen will help us understand perception, including what count as true and false perceptions. (AU) | |
News published in Agência FAPESP Newsletter about the scholarship: | |
More itemsLess items | |
TITULO | |
Articles published in other media outlets ( ): | |
More itemsLess items | |
VEICULO: TITULO (DATA) | |
VEICULO: TITULO (DATA) | |